Summary of the Lecture
Introduction
- The second of Professor O'Donovan's six Gifford Lectures at St. Andrews.
- Focus on the critique of ethics' disappearance from universities and public discourse.
Key Themes
-
Disappearance of the Good
- Previous lecture discussed the vanishing concept of the good.
- This lecture shifts focus to the disappearance of time.
-
The Relationship Between Good and Time
- Goodness is linked to existence and time; it is not merely a static concept.
- The goodness of God is eternal, yet our engagement with good is temporal.
- Actions and experiences are influenced by timing; the same action can have different values depending on when it occurs.
-
Nature and Time
- Time reveals nature's regularities, but it also shapes our understanding of fulfillment.
- The fig tree parable illustrates how nature can signal broader temporal truths.
- Fulfillment is a higher structure of finality that transcends mere maturity.
-
Moral Thought and Future Orientation
- Deliberation is a unique stance towards the future, distinct from recollection of the past.
- Moral actions are directed towards future outcomes, necessitating a belief in an ultimate good.
- The interplay between past experiences and future anticipations shapes our moral agency.
-
Practical Reason and Ethics
- Ethics must consider crises and uncertainties that challenge practical reasoning.
- The need for a moral faith that believes in the ultimate fulfillment of actions.
- The tension between prudence (short-term foresight) and principles (long-term ideals).
Conclusion
- The lecture emphasizes the importance of understanding time in ethical deliberation. For further insights on the implications of time in our lives, see The Value of Time: Insights on Life and Time Management.
- Future lectures will continue to explore the implications of these ideas, particularly regarding personal agency and constructive theological contributions to ethics. This exploration can be enriched by examining Exploring the Meaning of History: Events, Responsibility, and the Role of Christianity to understand how historical context influences ethical thought.
good afternoon welcome everybody both in saint andrews and around the world we are very pleased to have you with us
for the second of professor o'donovan's six gifford lectures here at st anders this year
we began on tuesday with the first of the first set of lectures the lecture series as a whole is divided into two
parts each consisting of three lectures the first three a critique of the ways in which ethics has been in
danger of disappearing from the university and from public discourse as a distinctive contribution to the way in
which we know and move around the world and professor o'donovan has begun to argue that the
disappearance of ethics is related to the disappearance of its distinctive horizons or goods or intentions
so in the first lecture he talked to us about the disappearance of the good and in this lecture he will move on to the
disappearance of time before discussing the disappearance of the person in the next lecture and then moving to the
second set of three in which he will give constructive theological contributions to the re-assembly or the
building up of ethics again we'll hear from professor o'donovan in just a minute before we do some
housekeeping points the first is that there will be a time for q a after the lecture the q a will
be handled by submission of questions you will see in the bar uh a question mark in a
speech bubble that will allow you to post your questions and we will then moderate and pose them to the speaker
there will not be time to answer all questions and both the publication and the response to
questions are at the discretion of the host and of the speaker so we may not take them in the order of submission and
as i say we will almost certainly not be able to get to all of them however professor o'donovan will be
able to see the transcript of the entire questionnaire of the entire q a after the lecture and
he will be very pleased to have feedback from you so please do raise your questions even if we don't get to them
the other thing to say about questions is that they are posted anonymously by default but we would be very pleased if
you identified yourself especially if professor donovan is familiar uh with you so please do put your name if you
would uh like it to be known and pose your questions as soon as the q a is live which will be at the end of the
lecture the other housekeeping point is that as our coordinator robin murray put it so
nicely this is the time of year when countries express their individual personality by setting different times
for the change of clocks british clocks are going back on the 31st of october but the us and the rest
of north america is not going back until a week later and there may be other changes in other
areas so please do make sure that you have the right time when we continue next week
without further ado professor donovan we're so pleased to have you with us it was a very enriching lecture on tuesday
and we look forward very much to this continuation over to you a meeting heavy with symbolism
occurred on october 1827 in weimar
the eminent hegel dropped in for tea with the elderly and yet more eminent gerta
and their conversation turned to dialectic the philosopher explained that this word
meant the regulated methodically cultivated spirit of contradiction which is innate in all men and which
shows itself great as a talent in the distinction between the true and the false
this produced an explosion from the old man let us only hope that these intellectual
arts and dexterities are not frequently misused to make the false true and truthful
hagel parents that such a use of dialectic would be mentally diseased
only eliciting the acid retort i therefore congratulate myself on the study of nature
which preserves me from such a disease there we have to deal with the infinitely and eternally true
now what offended goethe was not the commonplace idea that knowledge is reached by a zigzag course
it was the idea that knowledge was in the end no more than the contradictions involved
in reaching it knowledge he thought must be decisively achievable
one who knows something about nature is at the far end of an inquiry
beyond the ebb and flow of arguments occupying the observer's viewpoint dialectic on the other hand
admits no observers only participants and it defers an absolute truth
until the end of history by dialectic in effect hagel referred to history
as productive of truth that meeting of the 18th century philosophy of nature
where the 19th century philosophy of history was pregnant with
a very great deal of 20th century reflection from
one might say lenin to einstein now in our first lecture we attempted to recover the link asserted in ancient
philosophy between good and being something is good by virtue of what it is
not by virtue of what it is not and this brought us face to face with two related challenges
one was to conceive the harmony of two different ways in which we know good by enjoyment
and by action the other was to bring interview the temporal dimension
that governs enacted good so today we approach the frontier of time
another of the elements of moral thought that tend to disappear now it can seem that good and time are
detachable the goodness of god is self-sufficient and eternal though has no need of my
good the psalmist declared mine as belonging to this moment this agent
the good is complete and to worship and enjoy it is to be lifted up beyond the changing
times of life and action yet pure enjoyment without action
is not something we can easily conceive of knowledge of the good
commands our existence but existence is oriented to engagement in the world
worship of the good may indeed have a timeless quality of contemplation but it may also be a first action
a point at which the good that has no need of our good elicits
a particular good response from us and that is the logic that leads from the real good
to the temporal good something is good for us not only by virtue of what it is
but by virtue of when we meet it by its coming first or next
or later we speak of the right moment for an action
or even for an experience the same thing done or experienced
earlier or later would not be as good this first
or next or later cannot be separated from our experience of the real good
reality includes time as well as being now of course time may
be seen simply as a lens through which unchanging regularities of nature are
observed watch a rose bush for a year and you will learn about its annual
cycle of leafing body
and dying back watch many rose bushes for many years and you will learn of their other
natural features their lifespan varieties of habit conditions for success
and so on and all this will be essentially the same
whenever and wherever it is learned what i observe in my roses is more or less what my grandfather
observed in his time displays regularities natural regularities
including recurrent natural finalities or ends as a form of life
the rose is always developing in a certain direction towards a certain end in search of
nutrition in search of growth reproduction following a natural course from
immaturity to maturity but then of course it is also leading on to senescence and
death times display of nature's regularity brings us back at the end
to where we began gertard wrote last in unfamiliar
nights suzanne let the beginning and the end draw together as one
we may recall a line from gs eliot which says something very similar one way of putting this is to say that a
rose has a life but it does not have a history time reveals the rose
the rose does not reveal time theologians sometimes refer to what they call a circular idea of
time but in fact it's not time that is circular
it is nature time simply displays nature's circularity
we would do better to speak i think of a refractive idea of time time is a prism
through which the spectrum of nature is laid out in due sequence
now nothing in all of this could have caused goethe any uneasiness as a novelist and a dramatist
he was well used to displaying nature through time but suppose we turn
from the rose bush to another plant
we're advised by jesus of nazareth to learn the parable of the fig tree from that he suggests we may learn about
times that are coming for when the fig leaves we shall know
in the eastern mediterranean at any rate that high summer is at hand here the demonstrative relation of
nature and time has been reversed a natural form of being the fig responding naturally to its
context has become the lens through which we can mark the progress of time on a much
wider front towards a much wider finality and that finality we refer to not as
maturity but as fulfillment those two ideas are very different
maturity is observable fulfillment is not a fulfillment is the end of an end a
higher structure of finality superimposed on a lower one for ends form
pyramids human beings have organic finalities of health and strength which mature
usually somewhere between our 20th and 30th year but there are other regular finalities
that are equally human beyond that threshold are effective activity for example
depending as it does on acquired experience and not merely on physical strength
is at its height perhaps around 50. but then beyond that again there is a finality in existence itself
and the attainment of that cannot be predicted and measured like the two lower finalities
fulfillment is never recurrent it's always measured it's always aspired to
we know that we may succeed or fail in it but we're never sure whether we have
succeeded or failed call no man happy said solomon of athens until he's dead
yet even then we must reflect it's only a crude conjecture for we do not know that person's
aspirations from the inside so if we go then and look beyond the individual life and ask about the life
of a human culture or even the life of world history as a whole
it's clear that fulfillment is something we can only view from a position of relative unfulfillment
it's a frontier we may approach but not a territory we can have possessed
the idea of fulfillment is formed by our immersion in time our inability to narrate more than a fragment
of our past while we look forward to a future that is
at once a closed book and the focus of all our practical striving
jesus parable claims that like the fig leaf that signals the approach of summer
so certain indicative events may signal the fulfillment of history
but that fulfillment is something we have to learn how to see and how to talk about
it's not like talking about regularities of nature in the historicist thinkers of the 19th
century the term evolution was a term used not only for observable or conjectured
recurrent processes of modification in specific organisms but also for an overarching narrative of
bio history that would account for everything narrative is a sequential accounting of
events with a logic of its own it's quite distinct from classification and description
history is known through narrative and yet the thought of a narrative of
all history is very mysterious because our immersion in time forbids us
narrative access to the future of fulfillment a comprehensive world historical
narrative from the beginning to the end such as was attempted and outlined by
augustine with some self-awareness of what he was doing and not infrequently by medieval
imitators with rather less self-awareness is not what historians think of when
they speak of their craft what they do is recount segregated and partitioned episodes
they tell only one of many possible histories they can inquire objectively into the
history of commercial expansion in 18th century britain or they can inquire into the development
of political structures in ancient greece but they cannot acquire
enquire objectively into history as a whole for what history as a whole contains
is what is still to become of us history in the singular as they use the term
refers simply to the art or method of objective inquiry that establishes a narrative of some particular history
so when philosophy conceives the idea of a single all-embracing world history
a totality that is implied by all the partial histories joined up we have to wonder how such a history
could ever be told and by whom it could be told to us
who are situated somewhere within it to that question faith believes
that it may have an answer it would seem that a revelation that accompanied the unfolding of history
itself could give us an indication of its direction as a whole
learn the lesson of the fig tree it tells us all that about history
what of history and ethics now we plainly cannot entertain the idea that the good is simply an elaboration
of the progress of time a thought summed up satirically by c.s lewis
in the phrase goodness equals what comes next the good cannot be reduced to
indeterminate possibilities any more than it can be reduced to determine at facts
yet it still seems impossible to disentangle moral thought from future time
a practical disposition consists of intentions directed to the future reflective thoughts may move both
backwards and forwards at will through time but existence always moves in one direction out of the past into the
future and action has to follow that same direction
in proposing to act we reflect on how things have been in order to deliberate on how things
shall be action is not as is sometimes foolishly suggested
only a matter of the here and now the active present is inseparable from memories and
anticipations to try to live in a presence without a past or a future
would be an extreme form of dementia now about this temporal direction of moral thought
let us make three observations the first is this that deliberation
which is the name we give thinking about what to do is a stance in relation to time
that is quite different from all other stances it's different on the one hand from
recollection of the past it's different on the other from feeling in the present
its object is future the action that is presently a thought in the mind
must shortly become an event in the world and all our imagination is bent on how
the world will be when that happens yet this is not anticipation in the common sense which has to do with
predicting events when we deliberate on a course of action we do of course predict
but we also assert a claim to decide secondly it is an existential necessity that we
deliberate not only on our needs but on our life as a whole
we care not only for what we are about to do but for what we are going to become
we teach children this in the simplest way don't we by asking them
what you want to be when you grow up but what we have to become
is necessarily much wider than what we are to do it involves anticipations of longer term
future conditions over which we have no power to decide to devote oneself to the practice of
some art let's say music one must envisage your future if only conjecturally
in which certain conditions that are important to that practice are realized
we must envisage being better at that art than we are today
we must envisage making sacrifices for the art in other areas of life
we must envisage being constantly at risk of the loss of skills or competencies by
accidents and so on action life and history the three form a
linkage in our understanding uh
of the fulfillment of our agency andrew arrington writing from sydney in a question which we didn't get around to
on tuesday asked about that linkage and how it points to god and that brings us to our third
observation our agency points us to god ultimately not immediately
because we find that we cannot thoughtfully exercise it without some confidence
in an ultimate future so at least thought cut rather in tension
with his primary account of moral thought as conformity to the form of law which we glanced at briefly last time
since law offers a critique of instinctive appetites he argued the conscientious application of law
requires a higher object of appetite the expectation of a reconciled moral state
a state of blessedness to pursue any good under the discipline of reason
as we ought to pursue it we need to pursue it in the context of a last good
and ultimate vindication of reason itself and here
we need a power greater than anticipation we need a moral faith
a belief that ultimately the course of events will prove hospitable
to the efforts of moral life and action well what we draw from all this is that the use of moral reason
involves not only aspirations for the future but a number of different kinds of
cognitive relation to it yet a cooperative relation to the future is not at all like a cognitive relation
to the past the past is determinant it's known it's recollected it's narrated
it has happened the future so not out of reach
of or anticipation of hope of faith is essentially unknown never can we think of the future as we
do of the past not that is without forgetting our historicity and pretending to occupy some imaginary
lookout posts with views in both directions freedom encounters the future
as open and receptive ready to be determined by action
yet freedom also requires that we should be able to act fittingly in relation to the future
we're not doomed always to shoot our arrows into the dark we may anticipate enough
to aim responsibly in anticipating things we can use
imprudence a word which means of course foresight and prudence
is the capacity to interpret past experience and select from it that which promises some measure of
persistent regularity in the future allowing us a kind of partial probing of the future
even prudent anticipation is no more than an approximation to knowledge of course the hard knowledge on which it
depends is actually knowledge of the past an experience of processes
repeated with such regularity that we feel we may safely project them into the future always
pathetically but with some confidence or people say some processes are so broadly immune
from interruption that we can agree without stretching language too far
that we know something is going to happen
it would be too scrupulous to worry about a claim to know the our
sunset tomorrow night or the time of high tide tomorrow morning
but most predictions allows much less security than that and some people are clearly better at
making than others they're judicious in selecting the relevant predictive factors
in weighing their relative weight in understanding the degrees of contingency to which
they're exposed and sometimes we may claim knowledge of the future on other grounds altogether
from revelation or second side in which case our conviction does not depend on our capacity to predict
but all forms of future knowledge of any degree of certainty or
uncertainty are subject to this one condition they are not knowledge of fact
as knowledge of the past is fact fact means done
and what will happen is by definition what has not been done which is why
the conception of time that depicts us in the middle of a line that stretches equally out on either side indefinitely
cannot begin to convey the reality of our temporal existence which is an interface between what is
closed and done and what is open and waiting to do all those teasing questions of science
fiction about whether we could change the future if we only knew it can be given quite a short answer i
think if we knew the future as fact it would not be the future that we knew
there are no facts about the future a system of ethics that rests everything on foresight of future outcomes
such as the popular utilitarianism that came to dominate the imagination of
the english-speaking world for more than two centuries can only present us with a distorted
view of what prudence is prudence is concerned with the goods accessible to action
in the short term not with remote future goods resulting from long chains of causes and
effects long-term outcomes are much less open to view with an immediate dance of action
so that when we're solemnly told to judge what we do
by what will produce the best results in the end we're being told to anticipate what
cannot be anticipated rather than what can be anticipated what anyway could possibly count as the
end how long is the long run by which the short run must be measured
provence acting within its range is indispensable to good agency but its range is no greater than what
can be foreseen so a doctrine that in theory urges us to consider the distant horizon and judge
our actions by that tends in practice to cling to the short term and the predictable
and john stuart mill embraced this policy openly when he declared that actually living by a utilitarian ethic
meant obeying the most generally agreed rules of action which distilled the experiences
of predicting outcomes of the most people how then can ethics take note of the
future first of all it has to recognize that all societies
all individuals or planets even or galaxies
undergo crises which render the applications of practical reason effectively
impossible what do we conclude from that apocalyptic horizon before which as a
matter of fact we recognize we live one conclusion is that if practical reason cannot contemplate such scenarios
it's wrong to think about them thoughts that ethics was a description of life
in peaceful conditions what happened outside peaceful conditions well there was no concern of
everything entertain thoughts of crisis at least in public
and you can be seen as irresponsible as those who accurately foretold the economic collapse of 2008 discover to
their cost yet since modern reason cannot cut its connection with our interest in
existence and since our existential horizon is certainly not bounded by the predictable
we persist while fully accepting our ignorance of future conditions informing aspirations
in relation to them sometimes we want to benefit generations to come
sometimes we want to point the world to the kingdom of heaven these are intelligible moral actions
and in fact we usually admire them when we meet them but they certainly do not conform to the
limits of prudence existence reaches out to make commitments
for a future that cannot foresee if it could not do so there are various things we regularly do
that we wouldn't we would never marry perhaps and only rather rare rarely and
cautiously would we sign contracts well we can see why the original response
to the expansion of utilitarian modes of thought was and often has been since
an insistence on transcendent or absolute norms free of reference to particular pasts
and particular futures fiat justice as the proverb says
let right be done though the sky should form ages of moralism
usually sickened by what they take to be the arbiter-ness of public prudence and the pliable self-deceptions of pride and
rules return to a belief in duties that are known apart from reasons for them
inevitably in such ages the demands that people make on one another tend to be peremptory
and authoritarian kant's doctrine of moral law inspired 19th century europe to such a
reaction and we have now entered into another ex-such age with our well-meant but
crude doctrine of human rights but such reactions can never be more than reactions
duties may be self-evident occasionally in moments of clear self-discovery and crisis
but their self-evidence is like a flash of light that makes everything around it dark
in the end the only bulwark against arbitrariness is reasonableness and practical reasoning cannot develop
without some purchase on the future to act under the guidance of an absolute principle
unaffected by the paucity of our foresight we must know at least this one thing about the future
that by so acting we shall as jesus of nazareth expressed it save our souls
but such a faint such a faith needs to find some ground in experience what kind of ground could be available
i shall return in a moment to the forms that ground may possibly take first let me just pause a moment
over the question as to whether these two rival strategies for moral thought both of them form a list in shayla's
disparaging sense when he wrote about formalism in ethics to describe the one depending on future outcomes
which can of course never be known the other on immediate duties may not in fact be convergent strategies
text books of ethics such as professor holmes referred to in his introduction on tuesday and such as
still alas seem to govern teaching in schools and
colleges and so ensure the corruption of youth said that there were two rival theories
of practical thought deontological and teleological each professing to give a total account
of moral reason on its own formal basis these theories were such staffers dreams are made on
typical academic abstractions that no living human being could ever adopt or live by
one might even say that this two theory theory was the original formalism in ethics
propounding the false claim that moral thought was not generated by real events and real situations that
challenged our agency but was self-generated how then should we think of the
opposition of provence and principle which sometimes can be real enough
we should think of it simply like this moral reason which always mediates between the
present emerging from the past and the prospects open to the present they sometimes be led more prominently
by sets of existing circumstances and relations patterns of responsibilities may sometimes be led more
by future possibilities opportunities or dangers so there are some moral questions that
sound like how should a head teacher in a multi-racial school
respond when charges of racial bias are brought against a staff member of minority background
there are other questions that sound more like this how may we find a sustainable way of
achieving net zero emissions now either type of question may accommodate a broader or a
narrower range of factors in its answer and either type may be pursued far-sightedly
or short-sightedly the key point however is that the form of each question is
only a presenting moment in a substantial challenge to moral thought that is going to involve us if we pursue
it in a range of questions of both types competence in moral thinking requires versatility
it requires that we pay attention not only to all the material factors that condition the
situation but also in their turn to all the prospects which the situation offers so unwavering attention to the
responsibilities and the roles or a residence to be led absolutely
anywhere by an opportunity are both deficient moral postures deficient because irrational
as any attempt to stop practical reason in its movement between the past horizon and the future horizon
is bound to be irrational the disappearance of the future good
like the disappearance of the real good deprives ethics of an object the future good may disappear into
short-term anticipations based on very recent experience which is to say under recurrence
regularities that we have managed to observe or it may disappear into the vacancy of
a wholly unknown future which we cannot even begin to think about or welcome
for most deliberation we need to anticipate a definite future yet we do not need to
know that future in any detail at all a certain experience of life a certain sense of the space that lies
open to us ahead is enough for most ordinary purposes yet these anticipations are fragile
they can be swept away in a moment when things go as we didn't expect and our competence for agency
can be swept away with them to underpin agency then the disciplines of worship
encourage us to recollect goods further in the past and to entertain the hope
of a further future deliberation is very easily subverted by despair
for the horizon of the future is not always buoyant with hope but sometimes heavy with threat
jesus encourages us to grasp the future in two different ways by seizing immediate opportunities while
they are right before us and by fixing our minds on the ultimate
horizon yes at the same time he tells us to take no thought for the future
that is of course the future that is neither immediate nor ultimate that is too remote for prudent calculation but
still tempting to impractical speculation there's nothing contradictory in those
demands they correspond in fact precisely to the logic of deliberation itself
the hope of an ultimate future is and can only be a promise
not a prediction about such a promise it may seem that natural theology which
talks of only what can be said in general can say nothing
we may be tempted now to shrug our shoulders and conclude that any promise there is
will be given by revelation recognized by faith unamenable to any general description
but what cannot be described cannot be thought of if in the light of past promises claimed
and believed there is at least an outline of the shape of a promise that could illumine our ordinary
deliberations and actions faith and understanding may here as elsewhere prove
mutually supportive so let us think for a moment about one experience
as universally human and experience as could be wished which has played a very large part in
theologians attempts to describe the response to revelation and that experiences desire
only de lubac captured the theological headlines by speaking of
a natural desire for the supernatural neoplatonic metaphysics notwithstanding we ought to dismiss
any purported desire that has no reference to the future i can't desire what is
the closest parallels to desire are anxiety and hope and they too are future related
but while desire engages with the future it does not know the future it entertains possible future
knowing that they are merely possible but trusting that they are no less than
possible sometimes what we desire may also seem practical
and in that case the connection is simple between desire and
deliberation we begin to ask ourselves whether we should do something
to satisfy a desire and what we may do but desires are often impractical
offering no way through to deliberation we can desire for example the presence of someone who has died
yet what is impractical is not unthinkable we can certainly desire miracles
and we can know clearly enough what it would be like to receive the miracles we desire
and in that form desire may still assist deliberation by pointing it in the direction of belief
of hope of prayer so that even where it cannot resolve on
any other action it still finds something significant to be done
desire must always have some object that can be judged possible
if it has not it ceases to be desired and becomes despair delight becomes death longing
when all longing else is vain yates wrote so the point we came to in our last
lecture is reinforced the good that elicits our powers of agency is something
real in the broadest sense it belongs within the universe it has a
place it offers us at least ideationally something realizable
yet at the same time the object of a desire is a good that is absent desire implies wanting
in the literal sense that it's being without there's always a temptation to lose
sight of this and to expand the limits of desire too far desire does not include every kind of
appreciation of the good if it did it would embrace the present good as well as the absent good
and the price paid for such an expansion of desires to lose sight of its distinct character as an affection
desire is different from liking enjoy
willing and so on desire is a specialized emotion
we can do deliberately what we feel no desire to do and while desire may be a precipitating
factor that carries us to deliberation and action it's only one possible precipitating factor there are others
a sense of duty for example and other strong emotions may replace desire and prompting action as when we
strike out in anger weep in sorrow shout
in jubilation sometimes in the teeth of a strong desire to control ourselves so an absent good
is not a good that has no being it is a good that can be known as real but unfulfilled
pregnant with unrealized possibilities and that is how good excites desire in particular
it promises more of itself the promise is central to desire
there's a great difference between desire satisfied and a pleasant surprise in the one case the good was present to
the mind anticipated promise looked for in the other it is an unexpected discovery
what allows these ideational presences is the capacity of real goods to generate
promises of their own further realization the object of desire is desirable
because it is implied within a good already known desires are unintelligible
unless they're born out of constellations of goods that we already appreciate
elizabeth anscombe once famously illustrated this by asking philosophers to consider their
reaction to someone who claimed to desire a sorcerer of mud
to understand the desire we must see the place it occupies in the world of goods we desire to marry
because we're in love the more desire is focused on what is not there
the more arbitrary and pointless it appears even neurotic a composer
might sensibly desire to complete schubert's unfinished symphony a work of which two perfect movements
exist out of the classical symphonic four but it would make no sense at all to
desire to complete sibelius's eighth symphony a work of which the composer talked a
lot but not a note survives and perhaps none was ever written without a known good
the desire to supply what is lacking is empty and contentless but one cannot desire to supply a lack
unless the lag is actually felt and if we feel that schubert's new romantic aesthetic no longer requires a
symphony to have four movements then we will not feel that the unfinished is unfinished
so we will not desire to complete it so the question put to us by desire is this how do the goods we know and love
come to lack things and the answer brings us back to the refractive view of time goods reveal
themselves in temporal sequences appearing disappearing sometimes reappear
and desire is the heightened awareness of the coming and going of goods a distinct emotional response to
temporality it has its two characteristic notes of hope and of loss
desired goods are not only promises waiting to be fulfilled they are also reminders of things that
were good and have passed away nothing in desire itself can tell us
that the note of hope is more fundamental to it than the note of loss nothing in desire itself
can assure us that loss is always going to be open to recovery if the loss we experience when someone
dies is to be made good we shall certainly need to be told about
that from some other source desire will not tell us
but suppose we are told about it and told about it in a way that allows of belief
then we should find that the promise of an integrated final satisfaction addresses desires that we
quite ordinarily reveal and gives them a cognitive significance that they could not otherwise have
is there then a promise for history as a whole if there is it is the promise of a world
time conceived as convergent purposive and ultimately reconciled with itself
whatever promises we may encounter in the regularities of life the promise of history has to be given
us through a historical event a pointer to the end of history from within history and since history never repeats
itself our belief that we may know something of history and its end
will remain belief not without grounds but without a final verification
we shall know that a reading of history is true when its predictions have proved true
which is at no point within history the clue to history of where to find one must be given in a supremely meaning
bearing event or constellation of events which convey promise and illicit faith
this line of thought had its roots in the world of alexandria and judaism
which was open on the one hand to the teleology of plato and aristotle and open on the other to the historical
thinking of the jewish scriptures in the letter to the hebrews probably a production of alexandria and judaism
the promise of history is developed by a reading of psalm 95 a poem about the wilderness wanderings of israel that
concludes wherefore i swore in my wrath that they shall not enter my rest the author invites us to read this last
line in the light of another rest referred to in the
scriptures the rest of the creator at the accomplishment of creation symbolized and recalled in the
observance of the sabbath since he argues there was still another rest to be entered after the creation
was complete must we not think that the good of creation is waiting for an ultimate
fulfillment which we as the pilgrims of history are someone to enter
from a slightly different intellectual tradition one nursed in hebrew prophecy and
apocalyptic another first century writer known to us as john patmos
follows an interestingly parallel train of thought
the universe laid out in all its complex beauty and vitality before the creator's throne
is seen to yield a perpetually recurrent and repetitive hymn of praise but the prophet's view of this is
interrupted by one troubling feature in the hand of god
there is a scroll sealed seven times and the sight of it produces into tears
why because he confronts the very problem that we have been
confronting how the goodness of god in the repetitions and recurrences of reality
can ever be known if there is no clean clue to the meaning of historical events the question of the good of history then
arises from an insufficiency of the good of nature a good of nature could be good
only for an a historical observer everything that does not occur and repeat
is a threat to the sufficiency of the natural good a positive account of history is needed
not only to fulfill the promise of creation but to rescue it from reduction to meaninglessness
but this positive account is sealed against every attempt to penetrate it the only possible solution is a
proclamation week not the lion of the tribe of judah the rule of root of david has conquered
so that he can open the scroll and its seven seals out of the history of israel john
believes the meaning of world history will emerge but not in a straightforward line
not in a natural development in a celebrated transformation of images
the prophet who is being told to look for a lion sees a slain lamb
it's to that lamb in whom effective historical agency has been qualified by the experience of
historical suffering that the real disclosure of history and its
good is entrusted and that thought brings us to the third disappearing element in ethics to which
we turn in the next lecture namely that of personal agency thank you very much
thank you very much oliver that was magnificent and we look forward to about half an hour
of q and a um robin will now have switched the q a live
so please make use of the function uh in the chat
similar to the chat bar uh the q a bar simply type your questions and i will be able to see them there and to um
to to bring them to professor o'donovan's attention um
oliver while we wait for questions to come in can i ask you to comment you said that
there is nothing in desire itself that can tell us that hope is more fundamental to it than loss and that if
for example the loss of a death is to me be made good we need to be told about this from some other source desire
itself does not tell us i can i can see of course that the promise or the um the potential
actuality of a death made good of a resurrection is something that we cannot know except
from a promise or some kind of evidence that comes from without such as for example
from the resurrection of christ which we probably have in mind um do you have any sense that
the the fact of the desire of a continuance of life beyond the death that we see
again and again as irregularity in history has any kind of any kind of cognitive
value or significance where where does the desire come from if our entire experience throughout the
history of mankind has led us to see that death is the end yes yes
no i think that's a very well um take a point and we'll focus question it seems to me the situation
in which faith is placed when
confronting history with its contradictions and its meaning and its meaninglessness
is to decide to decide
whether meaning or meaninglessness has the upper hand in the end and it's that decision i
think that one cannot make simply by desiring it
desire can mislead us desire can persuade us to think we know what we don't know
it's a common psychological occurrence we know our desire is treacherous like this
but i think we can if
we have grounds for faith i think we can find supportive resonances in a natural theology of
desire which is in a thoughts that goes something like
this that if history and its life is in the end simply
swallowed up in meaninglessness then certainly our experience of desire is swallowed up with it that is to say what
i feel either means something terribly important or it doesn't mean anything at all i
mean i think that is always the point which we are we are thrust back to and it's not possible
to [Music] i think that i think this is the
argument i think i want to make it's not possible to pick and choose about meaning and meaninglessness
they are very they are very absorbing totalitarian embracing things
and once one says well of course the future of the world has no meaning it's an utterly open contingent thing one has
dumped a great deal of one's human experience without realizing it that i think is
what you're suggesting uh julius and i strongly support that thank you
we have a question from amy erickson could you speak to how disordered desire fits into your ethical framework
all feelings and desires of people it's part of our effectual resources it's
it's it's feelings are types of strength their capacities that
generate the possibility of action within us in general terms all feelings have to be
subject to thought um not that thought sometimes this is misconceived so thought is some kind of
an abstract um beautiful commander and feelings are a kind of jumble a mess of vitalities
and there is a kind of imposition like that the meaning of our feelings is imminent
to them they tell us something of themselves but we can remain in ignorance of what
they're telling us disordered desire i think is
an experience of desire that doesn't understand itself that
something is lacking in our lives we're deeply aware of something lacking in our lives
can be an intense feeling um a quite preoccupying feeling without
having the first idea really what it is that's lagging or how to set about finding out and
that is i think the meaning one gives the disorder desires it has nowhere to go it has
the desire comes the feeling can be on its own it's not self-interpreting we need to be able to interpret it
which we have to do by placing it alongside everything else we know about the worlds besides the fact
of our desire and of course the problem about very strong feelings is
that they hide from us all the other things we know about the world they push them out
so the we get to a state where the only thing we're aware of is how much we desire something
and the realities surrounding that situation don't as it were appear to us with the weight
that in other states of mind they would obviously have so recovering them
is as it were the recovery of the truth of the desire that we have that was a very nice question may i just
say thank you for that that's a very nice answer as well we have a question from bernd wonde it
goes as follows would it be a fair interpretation of your discussion of prudence deliberation
and desire to say that we must act confidently echoing the reformation distinction
between certitudo and securitas as opposed to thinking of time in terms of something to control or be controlled
by what i find when professor vanovich asks me a question is very often
that he is gently pointing me along a line that i ought to have gone and
failed to go and i suspect that this is another such moment um
i can see the fruitfulness of that obviously yes prudence
serves uh let me just think how to put this best prudence is not an end in itself it
serves our capacity to act and our capacity to act is not complete unless we can act in confidence and faith
exactly what we can say we know about what we're doing will vary from case to case sometimes we
have to knowingly take risks yet there is still something
we can be confident about even in the decision to take risk and that i think is
the sort of insight that um luther and his best successes have been able to bring
to this question of action the nature of confidence asking it faith is the root of action
and prudence is as it were giving us the resources for an act of faith i think i would take
it a little bit like that i think banovic himself could probably take it on much more effectively but that's as
far as i can go with it thank you and bernd if you would like to follow up
please please do so in the in the q a bar before we take a new question i have a
follow-up from somebody to your last answer to amy's question you answered that question on disordered
desire with reference to desires which are too strong what do you make of desires which are
too weak or too inconstant that's a desire is clearly eliciting some very nice questions i mean people
i'm going straight to the point here um thank you for that um what i say to that
is exactly the same as i say about desires that are too strong excellent
very good i'm glad we've settled that all right then we come to the next question from alan strange from loven um
following up from from tuesday so we have a future that is pointed to and a pointer within history
but what meaning does this give to present lordship of the one who is resurrected and was already resurrected
within history so we have a question about what what meaning does this give to the present lordship of the one
resurrected does what we have heard have a pneumatology i
shall want to say more to this um in a later lecture particularly in lectures six the last lecture of the
series in which i want to explore the pneumatology of ethics um
a bit further but so i think if i may ask alan just to hold back in patience just for a moment
i shall um say yes it obviously does um i mean action is
uh it its effect is in being present and available to us in our action
as we uh as we grasp and comprehend this the meaning
of this sign and the meaning of the history in which we act um
how we grasp it requires more care and i will talk about that in the sixth lecture
ellen we look forward to having you with us um until then and for that we have a question from johnny walker at
princeton how does the necessity of an ultimate future for practical reason as
recognized by kant relate to the need for that future's contingent revelation in history
does the former render the latter redundant i think not it doesn't
um what one can and may say to count
if we accept that the very crude description of him i've given is
near enough to the truth to discuss um what we can and must say to him is you know
that without a hope for the future practical reason cannot be a possibility in the end it's going to fail it's going
to lose confidence itself and see itself as having no reason we may always respond to that prospect
by saying so what is that not what facing up to harsh reality means um it's a question in its
form rather similar to the one that you professor wolf asks at the beginning um it seems to me
it points out to us and counts would point out to us that if we dump
a hope for the future we are dumping a very great deal about basic human experience with it including our
experiences ourselves as asians there are people who are prepared to do that
and perhaps all of us
at times of peculiar despair have been tempted precisely to do that
um and i think it is it is for that reason that all
encounters one must say that all kant has done is indicate a shape
that is waiting for something to fill it in reason thank you
um and alan says he is very happy to hold on until then you're assured um we have a question
from king ho lang here in saint andrews in your account can we say that god has desire
if so in what ways may divine desire resemble or differ from human desire relatedly would you say that your
account of desire here is one of natural theology there's plenty of talk about the desires
of god in the scriptures um this is part of the language of um
hebrew prophecy constantly and somebody so i think the question has to be what
we make of this whether this is an edifying picture describing something altogether rather
different of course from one angle it has to be um whatever god's desires are like
they're not just like ours obviously how would they be um uh one would end up with a totally
anthropomorphic picture as they were but is there something about desire that is
perfectly compatible with the divine being i think we have to say
yes if we believe that god acts
desire and action go together and if there is a meaningful sense to speak of divine action
um and the conditions of that are again things i want to come back to um
again in the last lecture i see i'm putting everything off till um the last lecture isn't that dangerous um uh but
if we are going to it's if we are going to speak of the possibility of divine action then
the possibility of divine desire makes sense around that that is to say god places himself in action in a position
where he has intentions wills that are in time yet to be fulfilled
um this is the difference one might say by speaking of god um
in himself in his assailty in the the the features of his being which belong to
him just as god and in the economy in history in his creating a world of time in which to be
present and those two languages will sound rather different
thank you king if you would like to follow up please do so in the q and a we have a question from andrew arrington
in sydney even with a disclosure of an ultimate meaning of history in the lamb that was
slain history remains opaque in certain respects
does ethics have an interest in broader and sometimes adventurous narratives about what is going on
that's a pretty good question for somebody for whom i think it is half past four in the morning
and who defies time by asking it tomorrow morning um
thank you andrew yes obviously ethics has an interest in such more adventurous narratives
and but it also has an interest in understanding their cognitive status
and distinguishing between what we might call speculation for speculation sake
about history and narratives that can
open themselves to some degree of demonstration no narrative of history as a whole
is capable of utterly demonstrating itself it's always going to be
indicated by signs within history which may then change that goes for christian narrative it goes for marxist
narrative very evidently for marxist narrative which in uh on some accounts has
now been decisively finished by events i mean whether or not that's true
um but so long as a narrative is proposed um that
deserves cognitively some kind of thought and examination uh and concerned then i think
ethics can't just dismiss it it is part of coming to terms with the reality of the world that is part of
realistic ethical thinking we have a question from jonathan chaplin who's giving you the get out of jail
free card right away by saying maybe this is in a future lecture but here's the question
is there a sense in which our eschatological orientation in faith towards the fulfillment of all desire
illuminates our orientation between the times towards
and our prudential deliberation about our desire for the fulfillment of natural ends such as marriage knowledge
art production of material goods and so forth yes there has to be i mean i think i
think that that answer is susceptible of a that question is susceptible of a direct
positive answer uh in that the the ultimate can only be ultimate in relation to a provision to provisionals
um the ways in which we understand such things as
a final good a reconciliation for history are all drawn from our appreciation of experience of
smaller temporary passing goods which we realize and see realized around
us um and can seek and sometimes bring about
including artistic goods cultural goods and so on and we have no
model for fulfillment accept
that which we understand from the world in its parts if
we imagine a divine message saying this world is to be fulfilled which then goes on to say
but this fulfillment is utterly different and of another kind altogether without
correspondence to any fulfillment that one experiences in the activities of this work we would not we would not know
what to make of that promise whether it was a promise or a threat in fact
and of a creator god and a providential god it is not an announcement that one would
credit um because
in this sense we go back to god and desire god himself has his purposes for this world in which there are
provisional ends and and indeed
in history sets up the conditions for the realization of such ends and commands
many we have a question from uh from robin here
and saint andrews robin beret i would like to ask about desire for imaginary objects must it be despair to
want a unicorn can we not desire something through myth ah
yes another very nice one uh thank you robin um we can desire that that perhaps the
giveaway in the question is the preposition through and uh
so long as the through his heart then yes
certainly we can i think there are things let's imagine somebody sitting down and reading
tolkien's lord of the rings and ask what kind of experience of
joy delight and perhaps desire such a really excited um
does such a person desire the perpetual triumph of the kingdom of
gondor or does i mean a re this is a reader in our own world of course um
while reading the book he may he or she may desire that the author will
uh ensure by the end the triumph of god or that's because imaginatively uh the reader is drawn into the book
as it were inhabits this world in which the triumph of gondor is a desirable object
standing back no longer reading it's impossible to desire the triumph of gondor but it's possible to recognize
that desire for such a thing is is a mediation of desire for what for something firm
something which that cultural object that imaginary object speaks to us
and the natural new objects are drawn into networks of significance in this way that is perfectly intelligible i
think and acceptable i don't know whether that's enough to satisfy you robin but
it's i think what i can come up with in the first moment thank you very much we have a number of
other questions in the q and a for which we don't have time at the moment so i will leave them to you
oliver afterwards and if you want to make reference to any of them in any future lectures please do they are very
interesting questions we are at time however and i will put in the q and a the um link for the next
lecture which will take place next week uh on tuesday thank you so much for a wonderful
evening you'll see that it's excited a lot of interest in the constructive proposals to come um but
also in the question of personhood and what is what is involved in personhood
and so we look forward to the to the unfolding of that in the next lecture and then uh the constructive proposals
in in the weeks to come thank you very much have a lovely weekend everybody thank you so much for joining us from
all the different time zones um please do come again next week and have a lovely weekend goodbye
you
Heads up!
This summary and transcript were automatically generated using AI with the Free YouTube Transcript Summary Tool by LunaNotes.
Generate a summary for freeRelated Summaries

The Value of Time: Insights on Life and Time Management
In this insightful talk, the speaker reflects on the nature of time, the importance of experiences, and effective time management strategies. Emphasizing that life is not merely about the passage of time but about the richness of experiences, the speaker shares practical tips for managing time effectively to achieve personal and professional goals.

Reviving Creativity: Insights on Philosophy, Art, and Culture Decline
Explore a deep conversation on the decline of Western creativity, the value of classical literature, and the importance of authentic expression. Discover how embracing curiosity, faith, and slow, thoughtful engagement with art and philosophy can counter modern cultural nihilism and sensory overload.

Exploring the Meaning of History: Events, Responsibility, and the Role of Christianity
This video delves into the philosophical discourse surrounding the meaning of history, the significance of events, and the implications of moral responsibility. It discusses the perspectives of notable philosophers like Nietzsche, Hegel, and Schelling, examining how their ideas shape our understanding of history and its meaningfulness in relation to Christianity.

Exploring Friedrich Nietzsche: Philosophy, Life, and Legacy
This comprehensive lecture delves into the life and philosophy of Friedrich Nietzsche, one of the most influential thinkers of the 19th century. It covers his key concepts such as the death of God, the will to power, and the idea of the Übermensch, while also examining his critiques of morality and culture.

Exploring the Future of Humanity: An Interview with Nick Land
In this engaging interview, Nick Land discusses his evolving thoughts on humanity's future, the implications of artificial intelligence, and the philosophical underpinnings of capitalism. The conversation delves into the intersections of technology, society, and the potential for human development in a rapidly changing world.
Most Viewed Summaries

A Comprehensive Guide to Using Stable Diffusion Forge UI
Explore the Stable Diffusion Forge UI, customizable settings, models, and more to enhance your image generation experience.

Mastering Inpainting with Stable Diffusion: Fix Mistakes and Enhance Your Images
Learn to fix mistakes and enhance images with Stable Diffusion's inpainting features effectively.

How to Use ChatGPT to Summarize YouTube Videos Efficiently
Learn how to summarize YouTube videos with ChatGPT in just a few simple steps.

Pag-unawa sa Denotasyon at Konotasyon sa Filipino 4
Alamin ang kahulugan ng denotasyon at konotasyon sa Filipino 4 kasama ang mga halimbawa at pagsasanay.

Ultimate Guide to Installing Forge UI and Flowing with Flux Models
Learn how to install Forge UI and explore various Flux models efficiently in this detailed guide.